side conditions and revisionism
play

Side conditions and revisionism David Asper o University of East - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Side conditions and revisionism David Asper o University of East Anglia 4th Arctic Set Theory Workshop Kilpisj arvi, January 2019 Apologies if you have heard this before. Special apologies to Vincenzo. Apologies if you have heard this


  1. Side conditions and revisionism David Asper´ o University of East Anglia 4th Arctic Set Theory Workshop Kilpisj¨ arvi, January 2019

  2. Apologies if you have heard this before. Special apologies to Vincenzo.

  3. Apologies if you have heard this before. Special apologies to Vincenzo.

  4. Forcing with symmetric systems of models as side conditions Finite–support forcing iterations involving symmetric systems of models as side conditions are useful in situations in which, for example, we want to force • consequences of classical forcing axioms at the level of H ( ! 2 ) , together with • 2 @ 0 large.

  5. Given a cardinal  and T ✓ H (  ) , a finite N ✓ [ H (  )] @ 0 is a T–symmetric system if (1) for every N 2 N , ( N , 2 , T ) 4 ( H (  ) , 2 , T ) , (2) given N 0 , N 1 2 N , if N 0 \ ! 1 = N 1 \ ! 1 , then there is a unique isomorphism Ψ N 0 , N 1 : ( N 0 , 2 , T ) � ! ( N 1 , 2 , T ) and Ψ N 0 , N 1 is the identity on N 0 \ N 1 . (3) Given N 0 , N 1 2 N such that N 0 \ ! 1 = N 1 \ ! 1 and M 2 N 0 \ N , Ψ N 0 , N 1 ( M ) 2 N . (4) Given M , N 0 2 N such that M \ ! 1 < N 0 \ ! 1 , there is some N 1 2 N such that N 1 \ ! 1 = N 0 \ ! 1 and M 2 N 1 .

  6. The pure side condition forcing P 0 = ( {N : N a T –symmetric system } , ◆ ) (for any fixed T ✓ H (  ) ) preserves CH: This exploits the fact that given N , N 0 2 N , N a symmetric system, if N \ ! 1 = N 0 \ ! 1 , then Ψ N , N 0 is an isomorphism ! ( N 0 ; 2 , N \ N 0 ) Ψ N , N 0 : ( N ; 2 , N \ N ) � Proof : Suppose (˙ r ⇠ ) ⇠ < ! 2 are names for subsets of ! and r ⇠ 0 for all ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 . For each ⇠ , let N ⇠ be a sufficiently N � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ 6 = ˙ correct model such that N , ˙ r ⇠ 2 N ⇠ .

  7. The pure side condition forcing P 0 = ( {N : N a T –symmetric system } , ◆ ) (for any fixed T ✓ H (  ) ) preserves CH: This exploits the fact that given N , N 0 2 N , N a symmetric system, if N \ ! 1 = N 0 \ ! 1 , then Ψ N , N 0 is an isomorphism ! ( N 0 ; 2 , N \ N 0 ) Ψ N , N 0 : ( N ; 2 , N \ N ) � Proof : Suppose (˙ r ⇠ ) ⇠ < ! 2 are names for subsets of ! and r ⇠ 0 for all ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 . For each ⇠ , let N ⇠ be a sufficiently N � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ 6 = ˙ correct model such that N , ˙ r ⇠ 2 N ⇠ .

  8. By CH we may find ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 such that there is an isomorphism Ψ : ( N ⇠ ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ ! ( N ⇠ 0 ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ r ⇠ ) � r ⇠ 0 ) (where T ⇤ is the satisfaction predicate for ( H (  ); 2 , T ) ). Then N ⇤ = N [ { N ⇠ , N ⇠ 0 } 2 P 0 . But N ⇤ is ( N ⇠ , P 0 ) –generic and ( N ⇠ 0 , P 0 ) –generic. Now, let n < ! and let N 0 be an extension of N ⇤ . Suppose r ⇠ . Then there is N 00 2 P 0 extending both N 0 and N 0 � P 0 n 2 ˙ r ⇠ . By symmetry, N 00 some M 2 N ⇠ \ P 0 such that M � P 0 n 2 ˙ extends also Ψ ( M ) . But Ψ ( M ) � P 0 n 2 Ψ (˙ r ⇠ ) = ˙ r ⇠ 0 . We have shown N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ ✓ ˙ r ⇠ 0 , and similarly we can show r ⇠ . Contradiction since N ⇤ extends N and ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 . N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ 0 ✓ ˙ ⇤

  9. By CH we may find ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 such that there is an isomorphism Ψ : ( N ⇠ ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ ! ( N ⇠ 0 ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ r ⇠ ) � r ⇠ 0 ) (where T ⇤ is the satisfaction predicate for ( H (  ); 2 , T ) ). Then N ⇤ = N [ { N ⇠ , N ⇠ 0 } 2 P 0 . But N ⇤ is ( N ⇠ , P 0 ) –generic and ( N ⇠ 0 , P 0 ) –generic. Now, let n < ! and let N 0 be an extension of N ⇤ . Suppose r ⇠ . Then there is N 00 2 P 0 extending both N 0 and N 0 � P 0 n 2 ˙ r ⇠ . By symmetry, N 00 some M 2 N ⇠ \ P 0 such that M � P 0 n 2 ˙ extends also Ψ ( M ) . But Ψ ( M ) � P 0 n 2 Ψ (˙ r ⇠ ) = ˙ r ⇠ 0 . We have shown N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ ✓ ˙ r ⇠ 0 , and similarly we can show r ⇠ . Contradiction since N ⇤ extends N and ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 . N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ 0 ✓ ˙ ⇤

  10. By CH we may find ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 such that there is an isomorphism Ψ : ( N ⇠ ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ ! ( N ⇠ 0 ; 2 , T ⇤ , N , ˙ r ⇠ ) � r ⇠ 0 ) (where T ⇤ is the satisfaction predicate for ( H (  ); 2 , T ) ). Then N ⇤ = N [ { N ⇠ , N ⇠ 0 } 2 P 0 . But N ⇤ is ( N ⇠ , P 0 ) –generic and ( N ⇠ 0 , P 0 ) –generic. Now, let n < ! and let N 0 be an extension of N ⇤ . Suppose r ⇠ . Then there is N 00 2 P 0 extending both N 0 and N 0 � P 0 n 2 ˙ r ⇠ . By symmetry, N 00 some M 2 N ⇠ \ P 0 such that M � P 0 n 2 ˙ extends also Ψ ( M ) . But Ψ ( M ) � P 0 n 2 Ψ (˙ r ⇠ ) = ˙ r ⇠ 0 . We have shown N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ ✓ ˙ r ⇠ 0 , and similarly we can show r ⇠ . Contradiction since N ⇤ extends N and ⇠ 6 = ⇠ 0 . N ⇤ � P 0 ˙ r ⇠ 0 ✓ ˙ ⇤

  11. In typical forcing iterations with symmetric systems as side conditions, 2 @ 0 is large in the final extension. Even if P 0 can be seen as the first stage of these iterations, the forcing is in fact designed to add reals at (all) subsequent successor stages. Something one may want to try at this point: Extend the symmetry requirements also to the working parts in such a way that the above CH–preservation argument goes trough. Hope to be able to force something interesting this way.

  12. In typical forcing iterations with symmetric systems as side conditions, 2 @ 0 is large in the final extension. Even if P 0 can be seen as the first stage of these iterations, the forcing is in fact designed to add reals at (all) subsequent successor stages. Something one may want to try at this point: Extend the symmetry requirements also to the working parts in such a way that the above CH–preservation argument goes trough. Hope to be able to force something interesting this way.

  13. A toy example: Getting a model of the negation of Weak Club Guessing with CH Weak Club Guessing (WCG): For every ladder system ( C � : � 2 Lim ( ! 1 )) (i.e., each C � is a cofinal subset of � of order type ! ) there is a club C ✓ ! 1 such that C \ C � is finite for all � . (Shelah, NNR revisited): ¬ WCG is consistent with CH. As with many classical results in the area this is done by building a countable–support iteration dealing with the relevant problem. At successor stages no new reals are added. The bulk of the proof is by far in showing that no new reals are added at limit stages either.

  14. A toy example: Getting a model of the negation of Weak Club Guessing with CH Weak Club Guessing (WCG): For every ladder system ( C � : � 2 Lim ( ! 1 )) (i.e., each C � is a cofinal subset of � of order type ! ) there is a club C ✓ ! 1 such that C \ C � is finite for all � . (Shelah, NNR revisited): ¬ WCG is consistent with CH. As with many classical results in the area this is done by building a countable–support iteration dealing with the relevant problem. At successor stages no new reals are added. The bulk of the proof is by far in showing that no new reals are added at limit stages either.

  15. A toy example: Getting a model of the negation of Weak Club Guessing with CH Weak Club Guessing (WCG): For every ladder system ( C � : � 2 Lim ( ! 1 )) (i.e., each C � is a cofinal subset of � of order type ! ) there is a club C ✓ ! 1 such that C \ C � is finite for all � . (Shelah, NNR revisited): ¬ WCG is consistent with CH. As with many classical results in the area this is done by building a countable–support iteration dealing with the relevant problem. At successor stages no new reals are added. The bulk of the proof is by far in showing that no new reals are added at limit stages either.

  16. The following is an outline of a proof of this result using side conditions and adding reals .

  17. We start with GCH. Fix Φ : ! 2 ! H ( ! 2 ) such that Φ � 1 ( x ) is unbounded in ! 2 for all x 2 H ( ! 2 ) . We build ( P � : � < ! 2 ) : Given � such that P ↵ has been defined for all ↵ < � , we define P � . q = ( F , ∆ , ⌧ ) is a condition in P � iff:

  18. (1) ∆ is a finite collection of pairs ( N , � ) such that N is an elementary submodel of H ( ! 2 ) , �  � , and � is in the closure of N \ Ord. (2) dom ( ∆ ) is a symmetric system of countable elementary submodels of H ( ! 2 ) . (3) F is a finite function with dom ( F ) ✓ � . (4) For every ↵ 2 dom ( F ) , if Φ ( ↵ ) is a P ↵ -name for a ladder system ~ C ↵ = ( C ↵ � : � 2 Lim ( ! 1 )) , then F ( ↵ ) is a condition for a natural forcing Q ~ C ↵ for adding a club of ! 1 , via finite collections of disjoint intervals, with finite intersection with C ↵ � for each � . (5) For every ( N , � ) 2 ∆ and ↵ 2 dom ( F ) , if ↵ 2 N \ � , then � N := N \ ! 1 is in the club added at stage ↵ . (6) ⌧ is a collection of pairs (( N 0 , � 0 ) , ( N 1 , � 1 )) such that N 0 , N 1 2 dom ( ∆ ) , � N 0 = � N 1 , and � 0 , � 1  � are in the closure of N 0 \ Ord and N 1 \ Ord, resp. Members of ⌧ are called edges . (7) q | ↵ := ( F � ↵ , ∆ � ↵ , ⌧ � ↵ ) 2 P ↵ for all ↵ < � .

  19. Main ingredient: Revisionism (copying information from the future into the past). (8) Given (( N 0 , � 0 ) , ( N 1 , � 1 )) 2 ⌧ , Ψ N 0 , N 1 ( ⇠ )  ⇠ for every ordinal ⇠ 2 N 0 (so N 1 is a ‘projection of N 0 ’). (9) Given (( N 0 , � 0 ) , ( N 1 , � 1 )) 2 ⌧ and ↵ 2 N 0 \ � 0 such that Ψ N 0 , N 1 ( ↵ ) < � 1 , all information carried by the condition at ↵ inside N 0 is copied on Ψ N 0 , N 1 ( ↵ ) .

Recommend


More recommend