why do corporate charters waive liability for breach of
play

Why Do Corporate Charters Waive Liability for Breach of the Duty of - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Why Do Corporate Charters Waive Liability for Breach of the Duty of Care? Holger Spamann Harvard Law School 6/5/2015 Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL


  1. Why Do Corporate Charters Waive Liability for Breach of the Duty of Care? Holger Spamann Harvard Law School 6/5/2015

  2. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default

  3. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default Why do they do that?

  4. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default Why do they do that? I First principles answer – theory/model

  5. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default Why do they do that? I First principles answer – theory/model I Simple cost-benefit argument

  6. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default Why do they do that? I First principles answer – theory/model I Simple cost-benefit argument I Implications: desirability is context-specific (e.g., charities)

  7. Overview Charters routinely waive monetary liability for bad business decisions by directors and managers (cf. DGCL 102(b)(7)) I if they didn’t, business judgment rule (BJR) would by default Why do they do that? I First principles answer – theory/model I Simple cost-benefit argument I Implications: desirability is context-specific (e.g., charities) I Unified theory of duties of care & loyalty (continuum)

  8. Argument in a nutshell

  9. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better

  10. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information

  11. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here

  12. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information

  13. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes

  14. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that

  15. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that I But the cost-benefit tradeoff is (usually) unfavorable

  16. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that I But the cost-benefit tradeoff is (usually) unfavorable I benefit of extra information low

  17. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that I But the cost-benefit tradeoff is (usually) unfavorable I benefit of extra information low I existing info good: stock price etc.

  18. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that I But the cost-benefit tradeoff is (usually) unfavorable I benefit of extra information low I existing info good: stock price etc. I extra info mediocre (courts 6 = business experts)

  19. Argument in a nutshell I Informativeness principle : using more information is better I always use free information I known exceptions don’t apply here I Courts (discovery) generate lots of information I e.g., alternative projections, negotiation notes I use needs to be calibrated, but caps etc. can do that I But the cost-benefit tradeoff is (usually) unfavorable I benefit of extra information low I existing info good: stock price etc. I extra info mediocre (courts 6 = business experts) I cost possibly high (opportunity costs of witnesses)

  20. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results

  21. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP)

  22. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere

  23. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action

  24. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability”

  25. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold

  26. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold I but: exception only concerns case where one relevant outcome completely unobserved (e.g., teaching-to-the test ...)

  27. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold I but: exception only concerns case where one relevant outcome completely unobserved (e.g., teaching-to-the test ...) I board, managers: there’s always the stock price

  28. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold I but: exception only concerns case where one relevant outcome completely unobserved (e.g., teaching-to-the test ...) I board, managers: there’s always the stock price I [Chaigneau et al. (2015): IP doesn’t hold if first-order approach is invalid]

  29. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold I but: exception only concerns case where one relevant outcome completely unobserved (e.g., teaching-to-the test ...) I board, managers: there’s always the stock price I [Chaigneau et al. (2015): IP doesn’t hold if first-order approach is invalid] I signal may not be useful for all/nothing decisions

  30. Basic Argument: Model = translation of standard principal-agent results I Holmström (1979): “informativeness principle” (IP) I optimal to use signal if it is informative somewhere I i.e., improves inference about agent’s action I weight on signal may be small – not “full liability” I Holmström & Milgrom (1991): multi-tasking: IP may not hold I but: exception only concerns case where one relevant outcome completely unobserved (e.g., teaching-to-the test ...) I board, managers: there’s always the stock price I [Chaigneau et al. (2015): IP doesn’t hold if first-order approach is invalid] I signal may not be useful for all/nothing decisions I but not harmful either

Recommend


More recommend