term rewriting equational logic term rewriting systems
play

Term rewriting Equational logic Term rewriting systems Termination - PDF document

Term rewriting Equational logic Term rewriting systems Termination Confluence Rapid prototyping Summary and Exercises Equational logic Reflexivity t = t t 1 = t 2 Symmetry t 2 = t 1 t 1 = t 2 t 2 = t 3 Transitivity t 1 =


  1. Term rewriting • Equational logic • Term rewriting systems • Termination • Confluence • Rapid prototyping • Summary and Exercises

  2. Equational logic Reflexivity t = t t 1 = t 2 Symmetry t 2 = t 1 t 1 = t 2 t 2 = t 3 Transitivity t 1 = t 3 t 1 = t ′ . . . t n = t ′ Compatibility 1 n f ( t 1 , . . . , t n ) = f ( t ′ 1 , . . . , t ′ n ) t 1 = t 2 Instance t 1 θ = t 2 θ Notation: ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 means t 1 = t 2 is derivable by the rules above starting form equations in E . 2

  3. Example: E := { x + 0 = x, x + succ( y ) = succ( x + y ) } ⊢ E 0 + succ(0) = succ(0) x + 0 = x Inst 0 + 0 = 0 x + succ( y ) = succ( x + y ) Inst Comp 0 + succ(0) = succ(0 + 0) succ(0 + 0) = succ(0) Trans 0 + succ(0) = succ(0)

  4. Soundness Theorem ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 ∀ E | = ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) . If then Proof. Assume ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 . Then ∀ E ⊢ ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) . Hence ∀ E | = ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) , by the soundness theorem for natural deduction.

  5. Completeness Theorem (Birkhoff) ∀ E | = ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 . If then Proof. Σ := the signature of E ∪ { t 1 = t 2 } V := the set of all variables for the sorts of Σ. Then T(Σ , V ) is the set of all Σ-terms. t 1 = E t 2 : ⇔ ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 = E is a congruence on the term algebra T(Σ , V ). A := T(Σ , V ) / = E A | = ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) ⇔ ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 (++) From (++), ‘ ⇐ ’ it follows that A is a model of ∀ E . Now: Assume ∀ E | = ∀ ( t 1 = t 2 ) . Then A | = t 1 = t 2 , since A is a model of ∀ E . Consequently ⊢ E t 1 = t 2 , by (++), ⇒ .

  6. A term rewriting system over a signature Σ is a finite set R of rewrite rules l �→ r , where r and l are Σ-terms, such that (i) l is not a variable, (ii) FV ( r ) ⊆ FV ( l ). t ≡ u { lθ/x } and t ′ ≡ u { rθ/x } t → R t ′ : ⇔ for some rewrite rule l �→ r ∈ R, some Σ-term u with exactly one occurrence of some variable x , and some substitution θ : X → T(Σ , Y ) → R is called the term rewriting relation generated by R .

  7. t → ∗ : ⇔ t → R . . . → R t ′ R t ′ t → R t ′ or t ′ → R t t ↔ R t ′ : ⇔ t ≃ R t ′ : ⇔ t ↔ R . . . ↔ R t ′ Any finite or infinite sequence t 0 → R t 1 → R . . . is called a reduction sequence . t is in normal form w.r.t. R if it cannot be rewritten, i.e. t �→ R t ′ for any t ′ . t ′ is a normal form of t , or t normalizes to t ′ if R t ′ and t ′ is in normal form. t → ∗ R := { l �→ r | l = r ∈ E } is called the term rewriting system defined by E . We write t → E t ′ instead of t → R t ′ .

  8. Example: E := { x + 0 = x, x + succ( y ) = succ( x + y ) } . 0 + (0 + succ(0)) → E 0 + succ(0 + 0) → E 0 + succ(0) → E succ(0 + 0) → E succ(0) Exercise: normalize succ(0 + 0) + 0 Normal forms: succ n (0) (that is 0, succ(0), succ(succ(0)) . . . ) 0 + (0 + succ(0)) ≃ E succ(0 + 0) + 0. Exercise: normalize 0 + (0 + succ(0)) using a different re- duction sequence.

  9. For a set E of equations and closed terms t, t ′ the following assertions are equivalent: ∀ E | (i) = t = t ′ ∀ E ⊢ c t = t ′ (ii) (iii) ∀ E ⊢ m t = t ′ (iv) ⊢ E t = t ′ (v) t ≃ E t ′

  10. Termination A term rewriting system R is terminating if there is no infinite reduction sequence t 0 → R t 1 → R . . . In a terminating term rewriting system every term has a normal form, but the converse is not true: R := { x + 0 �→ x, x + succ( y ) �→ succ( x + y ) , 0 + y �→ y + 0 } R is not terminating, but every term has a normal form. By removing the last rule the term rewriting system be- comes terminating.

  11. Proving termination A function µ mapping Σ-terms to natural numbers such that t → R t ′ ⇒ µ ( t ) > µ ( t ′ ) is called a termination measure for the term rewriting system R . Lemma. Every rewrite system that has a termination measure is terminating. Lemma. Let R be a term rewriting system such for every rule l �→ r in R r is shorter than l , every variable x ∈ FV ( r ) occurs in r at most as often as it occurs in l . Then R is terminating. Proof. The assumptions imply that the length of terms is a termination measure.

  12. Exercises. Which of the following term rewriting systems are termi- nating? R 1 := { x − 0 �→ x, succ( x ) − succ( y ) �→ x − y } R 2 := { f ( g ( x ) , y ) �→ f ( y, y ) } R 3 := { x + 0 �→ x, x + succ( y ) �→ succ( x + y ) }

  13. Theorem Given: R term rewriting system over Σ. A Σ-algebra, all carriers A s = N . f A strictly monotone for every operation f , i.e. n i > n ′ ⇒ i f A ( n 1 , . . . , n i , . . . , n k ) > f A ( n 1 , . . . , n ′ i , . . . , n k ) l A,α > r A,α for every l �→ r ∈ R and every variable assign- ment α . Then R is terminating. Show that µ ( t ) := t A,α is a termination measure, Proof. where α is an arbitrary variable assignment.

  14. Example R := { x + 0 �→ x, x + succ( y ) �→ succ( x + y ) } Define algebra A by 0 A := 1 succ A ( n ) := n + 1 n + A m := n + 2 ∗ m α arbitrary variable assignment. n := α ( x ), m := α ( y ) ( x + 0) A,α = n + A 0 A = n + 2 ∗ 1 > n = x A,α ( x + succ( y )) A,α = n + A succ A ( m ) = n + 2 ∗ ( m + 1) > n + 2 ∗ m + 1 = succ( x + y ) A,α

  15. R is confluent if for all terms t, t 1 , t 2 : if t → ∗ R t 1 and t → ∗ R t 2 , then there exists t 3 such that t 1 → ∗ R t 3 and t 2 → ∗ R t 3 . t � ❅ ∗ ∗ � ❅ � ✠ ❘ ❅ R R t 1 t 2 ❅ � ∗ ∗ ❅ � ❅ ❘ ✠ � R t 3 R

  16. R is locally confluent if for all terms t, t 1 , t 2 : if t → R t 1 and t → R t 2 , then there exists t 3 such that t 1 → ∗ R t 3 and t 2 → ∗ R t 3 . t � ❅ � ❅ � ✠ ❘ ❅ R R t 1 t 2 ❅ � ∗ ∗ ❅ � ❅ ❘ � ✠ R t 3 R Newman’s Lemma Every terminating and locally confluent term rewriting system is confluent.

  17. Example R := { a �→ b, a �→ c, b �→ a, b �→ d } R is locally confluent. R is not confluent, since a → R c and a → ∗ R d , but c and d cannot reduced to a common term. Exercises. (a) Add one rewrite rule that makes R confluent. (b) Remove one rewrite rule such that R becomes confluent. (c) Is R terminating?

  18. Theorem Every confluent term rewriting R has the Church-Rosser property : For all t 1 , t 2 t 1 ≃ R t 2 ⇔ there exists t 3 s.t. t 1 → ∗ R t 3 and t 2 → ∗ R t 3 t 1 ≃ R t 2 ❅ � ∗ ∗ ❅ � ❅ ❘ � ✠ R t 3 R

  19. Lemma If R is confluent and terminating term rewriting system then every term t has a unique normal form nf( t ). Theorem Let E be a system of equations defining a confluent and terminating term rewriting system . Then for all t 1 , t 2 ∀ E | ⇔ = t 1 = t 2 nf( t 1 ) = nf( t 2 ) In particular, the relation ∀ E | = t 1 = t 2 is decidable. Proof. t 1 ≃ R t 2 if and only if nf( t 1 ) = nf( t 2 ).

  20. Proving confluence: Critical pairs l 1 �→ r 1 , l 2 �→ r 2 variants of rules in R FV ( l 1 ) ∩ FV ( l 2 ) = ∅ . t subterm of l 1 which is not a variable, that is l 1 ≡ u { t/x } , x fresh occurring in u exactly once. tθ ≡ l 2 θ , where θ is a most general unifier. l 1 θ ≡ ( uθ ) { l 2 θ/x } � ❅ � ❅ � ✠ ❅ ❘ R R r 1 θ ( uθ ) { r 2 θ/x } ( r 1 θ, ( uθ ) { r 2 θ/x } ) is a critical pair of R . CP( R ) := the set of all critical pairs of R .

  21. Critical Pair Lemma A term rewriting system R is locally confluent iff for all critical pairs ( t 1 , t 2 ) of R there exists a term t such that t 1 → ∗ R t and t 2 → ∗ R t . Critical Pair Theorem A terminating term rewriting system R is confluent iff for all critical pairs ( t 1 , t 2 ) of R there exists a term t such that t 1 → ∗ R t and t 2 → ∗ R t . In particular, it is decidable whether a terminating term rewriting system is confluent. Proof. Critical Pair Lemma and Newman’s Lemma. Remark. For arbitrary term rewriting systems conflu- ence is undecidable (see e.g. Baader/Nipkov).

  22. Exercise R := { x < x �→ F 0 < succ( x ) �→ T succ( x ) < 0 �→ F succ( x ) < succ( y ) �→ x < y } Is R terminating? Is R confluent?

  23. Knuth-Bendix Completion Algorithm In order to transform a terminating term rewriting system R into an equivalent one that is confluent, do the following: 1. Compute CP( R ). If for all ( t 1 , t 2 ) ∈ CP( R ) there is a t with t 1 → ∗ R t and t 2 → ∗ R t then stop (in this case R is confluent according to the Critical Pair Theorem). 2. For any ( t 1 , t 2 ) ∈ CP( R ) such that there is no t with t 1 → ∗ R t and t 2 → ∗ R t , either add the rule t 1 �→ t 2 , or the rule t 2 �→ t 1 to R , such that the extended term rewriting system remains terminating (that’s the tricky part and not always possible, i.e. the method may fail here). Set R to be the extended system and go to 1.

  24. Exercise R := { g ( g ( z )) �→ c } Is R terminating? Is R confluent? If not, use the Knuth-Bendix Completion Algorithm to make it confluent.

Recommend


More recommend