phpe 400 individual and group decision making
play

PHPE 400 Individual and Group Decision Making Eric Pacuit - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

PHPE 400 Individual and Group Decision Making Eric Pacuit University of Maryland 1 / 24 Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of


  1. PHPE 400 Individual and Group Decision Making Eric Pacuit University of Maryland 1 / 24

  2. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. 2 / 24

  3. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. ◮ In many group decision making problems, one of the alternatives is the correct one. Which group decision making method is best for finding the “correct” alternative? 2 / 24

  4. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. ◮ In many group decision making problems, one of the alternatives is the correct one. Which group decision making method is best for finding the “correct” alternative? ◮ The different issues under consideration may be interconnected . 2 / 24

  5. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. ◮ In many group decision making problems, one of the alternatives is the correct one. Which group decision making method is best for finding the “correct” alternative? ◮ The different issues under consideration may be interconnected . 2 / 24

  6. Topics ◮ Voting in Combinatorial Domains: Anscombe’s Paradox, Multiple Elections Paradox ◮ Epistemic Voting: The Condorcet Jury Theorem ◮ Judgement Aggregation 3 / 24

  7. Group of voters Assume that there are an odd number of voters Candidates: Two candidates A and B Preferences: Rank A above B Rank B above A Indifferent between A and B Aggregation method Majority rule: A wins if more voters rank A above B than B above A ; B wins if more voters rank B above A than A above B ; 4 / 24

  8. Group of experts Assume that there are an odd number of experts Agenda: A single proposition P Judgements: Accept P /Judge that P is true Reject P /Judge that P is false Suspend judgement about P Aggregation method Majority rule: Accept P if more people accept P than reject P ; Reject P if more people reject P than accept P 4 / 24

  9. Proceduralist Justifications “[I]dentifies a set of ideals with which any collective decision-making procedure ought to comply. [A] process of collective decision making would be more or less justifiable depending on the extent to which it satisfies them... 5 / 24

  10. Proceduralist Justifications “[I]dentifies a set of ideals with which any collective decision-making procedure ought to comply. [A] process of collective decision making would be more or less justifiable depending on the extent to which it satisfies them...What justifies a [collective] decision-making procedure is strictly a necessary property of the procedure—one entailed by the definition of the procedure alone.” J. Coleman and J. Ferejohn. Democracy and social choice . Ethics, 97(1): 6-25, 1986.. 5 / 24

  11. Epistemic Justifications 6 / 24

  12. Epistemic Justifications “An epistemic interpretation of voting has three main elements: (1) an independent standard of correct decisions that is, an account of justice or of the common good that is independent of current consensus and the outcome of votes; (2) a cognitive account of voting that is, the view that voting expresses beliefs about what the correct policies are according to the independent standard, not personal preferences for policies; and (3) an account of decision making as a process of the adjustment of beliefs, adjustments that are undertaken in part in light of the evidence about the correct answer that is provided by the beliefs of others. (p. 34) ” J. Cohen. An epistemic conception of democracy . Ethics, 97(1): 26-38, 1986. 6 / 24

  13. “Condorcet begins with the premise that the object of government is to make decisions that are in the best interest of society. This leads naturally to the question: what voting rules are most likely to yield good outcomes?.... 7 / 24

  14. “Condorcet begins with the premise that the object of government is to make decisions that are in the best interest of society. This leads naturally to the question: what voting rules are most likely to yield good outcomes?.... Why should we buy the idea, though, that there really is such a thing as an objectively “best” choice? Aren’t values relative, and isn’t the point of voting to strike a balance between conflicting opinions, not to determine a correct one?” H. P. Young. Optimal Voting Rules . The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9:1, pgs. 51 - 64, 1995. 7 / 24

  15. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. 8 / 24

  16. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. ◮ In many group decision making problems, one of the alternatives is the correct one. Which group decision making method is best for finding the “correct” alternative? 8 / 24

  17. ◮ Group decision problems often exhibit a combinatorial structure . For example, selecting a committee from a set of candidates or voting on a number of yes/no issues in a referendum. ◮ In many group decision making problems, one of the alternatives is the correct one. Which group decision making method is best for finding the “correct” alternative? ◮ The different issues under consideration may be interconnected . 8 / 24

  18. Topics ◮ Voting in Combinatorial Domains: Anscombe’s Paradox, Multiple Elections Paradox ◮ Epistemic Voting: The Condorcet Jury Theorem ◮ Judgement Aggregation 9 / 24

  19. Suppose there are equally skilled individuals, each with a probability p > 1 / 2 of “choosing correctly”. 10 / 24

  20. Suppose there are equally skilled individuals, each with a probability p > 1 / 2 of “choosing correctly”. Let F be a decision method. π ( F , p ) is the probability of getting the answer correct, given the skills of each individual p . 10 / 24

  21. Expert rule π ( F e , p ) = p 11 / 24

  22. Majority Rule π ( F m , p ) = p 3 + 3 p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability everyone is correct is p 3 The probability that 1 and 2 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 2 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 1 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) 12 / 24

  23. Majority Rule π ( F m , p ) = p 3 + 3 p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability everyone is correct is p 3 The probability that 1 and 2 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 2 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 1 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) 12 / 24

  24. Majority Rule π ( F m , p ) = p 3 + 3 p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability everyone is correct is p 3 The probability that 1 and 2 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 2 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 1 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) 12 / 24

  25. Majority Rule π ( F m , p ) = p 3 + 3 p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability everyone is correct is p 3 The probability that 1 and 2 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 2 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) The probability that 1 and 3 are correct: p 2 ( 1 − p ) 12 / 24

  26. Theorem . When there are three voters, each with a probability p > 1 / 2 of choosing correctly, then majority rule is preferred to the expert rule. 13 / 24

  27. Theorem . When there are three voters, each with a probability p > 1 / 2 of choosing correctly, then majority rule is preferred to the expert rule. Theorem . Assume p 1 ≥ p 2 > p 3 > 1 / 2, then the simple majority rule is preferred to the expert rule. 13 / 24

  28. Consider 3 votes, each with a confidence level p = 2 / 3. 14 / 24

  29. Consider 3 votes, each with a confidence level p = 2 / 3. The probability of at least m voters being correct is: n � n � � ∗ p h ∗ ( 1 − p ) n − h h h = m 14 / 24

  30. Consider 3 votes, each with a confidence level p = 2 / 3. The probability of at least m voters being correct is: n � n � � ∗ p h ∗ ( 1 − p ) n − h h h = m � 3 � � 3 � ∗ ( 2 / 3 ) 2 ∗ 1 / 3 1 + 2 / 3 3 ∗ 1 / 3 0 2 3 14 / 24

  31. Consider 3 votes, each with a confidence level p = 2 / 3. The probability of at least m voters being correct is: n � n � � ∗ p h ∗ ( 1 − p ) n − h h h = m � 3 � � 3 � ∗ ( 2 / 3 ) 2 ∗ 1 / 3 1 + 2 / 3 3 ∗ 1 / 3 0 2 3 = 3 ∗ 4 / 27 + 1 ∗ 8 / 27 = 20 / 27 14 / 24

  32. Condorcet Jury Theorem State of the world x takes values 0 and 1 R i is the event that voter i votes correctly. M n is the event that a majority of n member electorate votes correctly. 15 / 24

  33. Condorcet Jury Theorem State of the world x takes values 0 and 1 R i is the event that voter i votes correctly. M n is the event that a majority of n member electorate votes correctly. Independence R 1 , R 2 , . . . are independent conditional on x Competence : for each x ∈ { 0 , 1 } , Pr ( R i | x ) > 1 2 15 / 24

Recommend


More recommend