contextual categories as monoids in a category of
play

Contextual categories as monoids in a category of collections (Work - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Contextual categories as monoids in a category of collections (Work in progress) Chaitanya Leena Subramaniam 1 Peter LeFanu Lumsdaine 2 1 IRIF, Universit Paris Diderot 2 Dept. of Mathematics, Stockholm University HoTT 2019, Pittsburgh 1 / 27


  1. Contextual categories as monoids in a category of collections (Work in progress) Chaitanya Leena Subramaniam 1 Peter LeFanu Lumsdaine 2 1 IRIF, Université Paris Diderot 2 Dept. of Mathematics, Stockholm University HoTT 2019, Pittsburgh 1 / 27

  2. Goal: A “nice” definition of dependently typed theory We want to give a good, algebraic description of a theory expressed in the language of Martin-Löf’s framework of dependent types. 2 / 27

  3. Goal: A “nice” definition of dependently typed theory We want to give a good, algebraic description of a theory expressed in the language of Martin-Löf’s framework of dependent types. Problem A theory is a syntactic object, and these don’t obviously have a nice algebraic definition. Well-known syntactic definitions of what such a theory should be are GATs [Car78] and FOLDS signatures [Pal16]. 2 / 27

  4. Disclaimer We don’t consider any type formers ( Id , Π , U , etc.) in our theories — i.e. the syntactic category of a “dependently typed theory” will simply be a contextual category with no additional structure. (Eventually, we’d like to add them one by one.) 3 / 27

  5. We’d like: ▶ A good category with a nice description (not explicitly involving any syntax). ▶ But each of whose objects corresponds canonically to a syntactic dependently typed theory (and the same for morphisms). A motivating example is the category of symmetric S et -operads, which correspond to certain algebraic theories. 4 / 27

  6. Our proposal for a category of theories Recall A contextual category is a small category C “resembling” the syntactic category of a dependently typed theory. 5 / 27

  7. Our proposal for a category of theories Our proposed definition A theory is an I -contextual category , where I is a finitely branching inverse category ( I is the type signature of the theory). The category C xlCat ( I ) of these embeds into the category of contextual categories under the free contextual category on I . C xlCat ( I ) C ( I ) / C xlCat 5 / 27

  8. Nice features ▶ C xlCat ( I ) is the category of monoids in a presheaf category of “ I -coloured collections” (analogous to operads and polynomial monads). ▶ From any T ∈ C xlCat ( I ) , we can recover a syntax that presents it (its underlying collection). Drawback May not encompass all generalised algebraic theories. 6 / 27

  9. Goals of this talk 1. Justify the following: A dependently typed theory or I -contextual category is the data of 1. a finitely branching inverse category I 2. and a finitary monad on S et I . 7 / 27

  10. Goals of this talk 1. Justify the following: A dependently typed theory or I -contextual category is the data of 1. a finitely branching inverse category I 2. and a finitary monad on S et I . Example/particular case A multisorted Lawvere theory is the data of 1. a set S (always a fin. branching inverse category) 2. and a finitary monad on S et S . 7 / 27

  11. 2. To convey the picture: Every operation in a dependently typed theory takes a finite cell complex as in- put, and outputs a cell. (This is related to Burroni-Leinster T - f operads.) 8 / 27

  12. Example/particular case An operation in a multisorted Lawvere theory takes a finite coproduct of points {• , • , • , •} as input, and outputs a point. f • 9 / 27

  13. Examples of inverse categories ▶ Every set S . 10 / 27

  14. Examples of inverse categories ▶ Every set S . ▶ Every Reedy category has a (wide non-full) inverse subcategory (e.g. ∆ op + ) 10 / 27

  15. Examples of inverse categories ▶ Every set S . ▶ Every Reedy category has a (wide non-full) inverse subcategory (e.g. ∆ op + ) ▶ . . . s t G 1 G 2 G op = O op (opetopes). s t s t G 0 G 1 s t G 0 10 / 27

  16. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. 11 / 27

  17. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. ▶ The identity monads on G raph , S et G op , S et O op , S et ∆ op + . 11 / 27

  18. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. ▶ The identity monads on G raph , S et G op , S et O op , S et ∆ op + . ▶ The free-category monad on G raph . 11 / 27

  19. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. ▶ The identity monads on G raph , S et G op , S et O op , S et ∆ op + . ▶ The free-category monad on G raph . ▶ The free-strict- ω -category monad on S et G op . 11 / 27

  20. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. ▶ The identity monads on G raph , S et G op , S et O op , S et ∆ op + . ▶ The free-category monad on G raph . ▶ The free-strict- ω -category monad on S et G op . ▶ The free- weak - ω -category monad on S et G op . 11 / 27

  21. Examples of dependently typed theories ▶ Every multisorted Lawvere theory. ▶ The identity monads on G raph , S et G op , S et O op , S et ∆ op + . ▶ The free-category monad on G raph . ▶ The free-strict- ω -category monad on S et G op . ▶ The free- weak - ω -category monad on S et G op . ▶ For T : S et I → S et I a finitary cartesian monad, every T -operad (à la Burroni-Leinster). ▶ And many more... 11 / 27

  22. Syntactic example Let I = { G 2 ⇒ G 1 ⇒ G 0 } with the (co)globular relations. Then I corresponds to the following type signature. ⊢ G 0 x , y : G 0 ⊢ G 1 ( x , y ) x , y : G 0 , f , g : G 1 ( x , y ) ⊢ G 2 ( f , g ) The theory of 2 -categories (or even of bicategories) is a collection of terms and definitional equalities expressible in this type signature. 12 / 27

  23. Preliminaries 13 / 27

  24. ▶ Let I be a small category. 14 / 27

  25. ▶ Let I be a small category. ▶ Fin ( I ) is the category of finitely presentable covariant → S et I presheaves on I . Denote the dense inclusion Fin ( I ) ֒ by E . 14 / 27

  26. ▶ Let I be a small category. ▶ Fin ( I ) is the category of finitely presentable covariant → S et I presheaves on I . Denote the dense inclusion Fin ( I ) ֒ by E . ▶ Recall that Fin ( I ) is the finite-colimit completion of I op . When I is a set, Fin ( I ) is the also the finite-coproduct completion of I . 14 / 27

  27. Cartesian collections The presheaf category C oll I := S et I × Fin ( I ) is called the category of I -collections . (Intuition: F ∈ C oll I should be thought of as a term signature — for each context Γ ∈ Fin ( I ) and each sort i ∈ I , F ( i , Γ) is the set of operations with input Γ and output sort i .) 15 / 27

  28. Composition of cartesian collections I -collections can be composed via substitution : ∫ Θ ∈ Fin ( I ) G ( i , Θ) × S et I (Θ , F ( − , Γ)) . G ◦ F ( i , Γ) := ( C oll I , ◦ , E ) is a (non-symmetric) monoidal category , where → S et I . E : Fin ( I ) ֒ 16 / 27

  29. Cartesian collections and endofunctors on S et I The functor Lan E ( − ) : C oll I → [ S et I , S et I ] of left Kan extension → S et I is (1) fully faithful and (2) monoidal . along E : Fin ( I ) ֒ F S et I Fin ( I ) ∼ = (1) E Lan E F S et I Lan E ( F ◦ G ) ∼ Lan E E ∼ = Lan E F ◦ Lan E G ; = id (2) 17 / 27

  30. Consequence → M nd ( S et I ) Lan E − : M on ( C oll I , ◦ , E ) ֒ The category of monoids in C oll I is a full subcategory of the category of monads on S et I . It is none other than the category of finitary monads on S et I . 18 / 27

  31. Consequence → M nd ( S et I ) Lan E − : M on ( C oll I , ◦ , E ) ֒ The category of monoids in C oll I is a full subcategory of the category of monads on S et I . It is none other than the category of finitary monads on S et I . Remarks ▶ We have only used that I is a small category. ▶ M on ( C oll I , ◦ , E ) is also known as the category of monads with arities (Weber) or Lawvere theories with arities (Melliès) for → S et I . the arities E : Fin ( I ) ֒ 18 / 27

  32. Contextual categories as monoids in collections 19 / 27

  33. Inverse categories Definition An inverse category is: ▶ a small category I , ▶ whose objects are graded by “dimension” dim : Ob ( I ) → O rd , ▶ such that non-identity morphisms strictly decrease dimension, ▶ and that has no infinite strictly descending chains. 20 / 27

  34. Inverse categories Definition An inverse category is: ▶ a small category I , ▶ whose objects are graded by “dimension” dim : Ob ( I ) → O rd , ▶ such that non-identity morphisms strictly decrease dimension, ▶ and that has no infinite strictly descending chains. I is finitely branching if the tree i / I generated by every i ∈ I is finite. 20 / 27

  35. Main observation Proposition (L.S., LeFanu Lumsdaine) Let I be a finitely branching inverse category. Then Fin ( I ) op is equivalent to a contextual category C ( I ) (the free contextual category on I ). 21 / 27

  36. Main observation Proposition (L.S., LeFanu Lumsdaine) Let I be a finitely branching inverse category. Then Fin ( I ) op is equivalent to a contextual category C ( I ) (the free contextual category on I ). (Note: The structure of a contextual category does not transfer across an equivalence of categories.) 21 / 27

Recommend


More recommend