quantum statistical comparison and majorization
play

Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their applications to generalized resource theories) Francesco Buscemi (Nagoya University) Quantum Foundations Seminar Series, Perimeter Institute 26 February 2019 Guiding idea: generalized


  1. Quantum Statistical Comparison and Majorization (and their applications to generalized resource theories) Francesco Buscemi (Nagoya University) Quantum Foundations Seminar Series, Perimeter Institute 26 February 2019

  2. Guiding idea: generalized resource theories as order theories for stochastic (probabilistic) structures 0/31

  3. The Precursor: Majorization

  4. Lorenz Curves and Majorization Lorenz curve for probability distribution • two probability distributions, p = ( p 1 , . . . , p n ) p = ( p 1 , · · · , p n ) : and q = ( q 1 , . . . , q n ) i =1 p ↓ • truncated sums P ( k ) = � k i and i =1 q ↓ Q ( k ) = � k i , for all k = 1 , . . . , n • p majorizes q , i.e., p � q , whenever P ( k ) ≥ Q ( k ) , for all k • minimal element: uniform distribution e = n − 1 (1 , 1 , · · · , 1) Hardy, Littlewood, and P´ olya (1929) ( x k , y k ) = ( k/n, P ( k )) , 1 ≤ k ≤ n p � q ⇐ ⇒ q = M p , for some bistochastic matrix M . 1/31

  5. Blackwell’s Extensions

  6. Statistical Decision Problems experiment decision Θ − → X − → U � � � − → − → θ x u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) payoff is ℓ ( θ, u ) ∈ R Definition A statistical model (or experiment ) is a triple w = � Θ , X , w � , a statistical decision problem (or game ) is a triple g = � Θ , U , ℓ � . 2/31

  7. Playing Games with Experiments experiment decision Θ − → X − → U • the experiment (model) is given , i.e., it is the “resource” � � � • the decision instead can be optimized θ − → x − → u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) Definition The expected payoff of a statistical model w = � Θ , X , w � w.r.t. a decision problem g = � Θ , U , ℓ � is given by ℓ ( θ, u ) d ( u | x ) w ( x | θ ) | Θ | − 1 . � def E g [ w ] = max d ( u | x ) u,x,θ 3/31

  8. Comparing Statistical Models 1/2 Second model: w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ ( y | θ ) � First model: w = � Θ , X , w ( x | θ ) � experiment experiment decision decision − → X − → U − → Y − → U Θ Θ � � � � � � − → − → − → − → θ x u θ x u w ( x | θ ) d ( u | x ) w ′ ( y | θ ) d ′ ( u | y ) For a fixed decision problem g = � Θ , U , ℓ � , the expected payoffs E g [ w ] and E g [ w ′ ] can always be ordered. 4/31

  9. Comparing Statistical Models 2/2 Definition (Information Preorder) If the model w = � Θ , X , w � is better than model w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ � for all decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � , then we say that w is more informative than w ′ , and write w � w ′ . Problem. Can we visualize the information morphism � more concretely? 5/31

  10. Information Morphism = Statistical Sufficiency Blackwell-Sherman-Stein Theorem (1948-1953) Given two experiments with the same parameter space, w = � Θ , X , w � and w ′ = � Θ , Y , w ′ � , the condition w � w ′ holds iff there exists a conditional probability ϕ ( y | x ) such that w ′ ( y | θ ) = � x ϕ ( y | x ) w ( x | θ ) . noise Θ − → Y Θ − → X − → Y � � = � � � − → − → − → θ y θ x y David H. Blackwell (1919-2010) w ′ ( y | θ ) w ( x | θ ) ϕ ( y | x ) 6/31

  11. Special Case: Dichotomies • two pairs of probability distributions, i.e., two dichotomies , ( p 1 , p 2 ) and ( q 1 , q 2 ) , of dimension m and n , respectively 2 and q j 1 /q j • relabel entries such that ratios p i 1 /p i 2 are nonincreasing • construct the truncated sums P 1 , 2 ( k ) = � k i =1 p i 1 , 2 and Q 1 , 2 ( k ) • ( p 1 , p 2 ) � ( q 1 , q 2 ) iff the relative Lorenz curve of the former is never below that of the latter Relative Lorenz curves: Blackwell’s Theorem for Dichotomies (1953) ( x k , y k ) = ( P 2 ( k ) , P 1 ( k )) ( p 1 , p 2 ) � ( q 1 , q 2 ) ⇐ ⇒ q i = M p i , for some stochastic 7/31 matrix M .

  12. The Viewpoint of Communication Theory

  13. Statistics vs Information Theory • Statistical models are mathematically equivalent to noisy channels: • However: while in statistics the input is inaccessible (Nature does not bother with coding!) • in communication theory a sender does code ! 8/31

  14. From Decision Problems to Decoding Problems Definition (Decoding Problems) Given a channel w = �X , Y , w ( y | x ) � , a decoding problem is defined by an encoding e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � and the payoff function is the optimum guessing probability: d ( m | y ) w ( y | x ) e ( x | m ) |M| − 1 = 2 − H min ( M | Y ) � def E e [ w ] = max d ( m | y ) m,x,y

  15. Comparison of Classical Noisy Channels Consider two discrete noisy channels w and w ′ with the same input alphabet Theorem Given the following pre-orders 1. degradability: there exists ϕ ( z | y ) : w ′ ( x | z ) = � y ϕ ( z | y ) w ( y | x ) 2. noisiness: for all encodings e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � , H ( M | Y ) ≤ H ( M | Z ) 3. ambiguity: for all encodings e = �M , X , e ( x | m ) � , H min ( M | Y ) ≤ H min ( M | Z ) ⇒ (2) (data-processing inequality), (2) � ⇒ (1) (K¨ we have: (1) = = orner and Marton, 1977), but (1) ⇐ ⇒ (3) (FB, 2016).

  16. Some Classical Channel Morphisms Output degrading: Input degrading: Full coding (Shannon’s “channel inclusion”, 1958): 11/31

  17. Extensions to the Quantum Case

  18. Some Quantum Channel Morphisms Output degrading: Input degrading: Quantum coding with forward CC: 12/31

  19. Output Degradability

  20. Comparison of Quantum Statistical Models 1/2 Quantum statistical models as cq-channels: Formulation below from: A.S. Holevo, Statistical Decision Theory for Quantum Systems , 1973. classical case quantum case • decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � • decision problems g = � Θ , U , ℓ � � Θ , H S , { ρ θ � • experiments w = � Θ , X , { w ( x | θ ) }� • quantum experiments E = S } • POVMs { P u • decisions d ( u | x ) S : u ∈ U} x d ( u | x ) w ( x | θ ) | Θ | − 1 � ρ θ S P u � | Θ | − 1 • p c ( u, θ ) = � • p q ( u, θ ) = Tr S � � • E g [ w ] = max ℓ ( θ, u ) p c ( u, θ ) • E g [ E ] = max ℓ ( θ, u ) p q ( u, θ ) { P u d ( u | x ) S }

  21. Comparison of Quantum Statistical Models 2/2 What follows is from: FB, Comm. Math. Phys., 2012 � Θ , H S , { ρ θ � • consider two quantum statistical models E = S } and E ′ = � Θ , H S ′ , { σ θ � S ′ } • information ordering : E � E ′ iff E g [ E ] ≥ E g [ E ′ ] for all g • E � E ′ iff there exists a quantum statistical morphism (essentially, a PTP map) M : L ( H S ) → L ( H S ′ ) such that M ( ρ θ S ) = σ θ S ′ for all θ • complete information ordering : E � c E ′ iff E ⊗ F � E ′ ⊗ F for all ancillary models F (in fact, one informationally complete model suffices) • E � c E ′ iff there exists a CPTP map N : L ( H S ) → L ( H S ′ ) such that N ( ρ θ S ) = σ θ S ′ for all θ • if E ′ is abelian , then E � c E ′ iff E � E ′ 14/31

  22. Comparison of Quantum Channels 1/2 Definition (Quantum Decoding Problems) Given a quantum channel N : A → B , a quantum decoding problem is defined by a bipartite state ω RA and the payoff function is the optimum singlet fraction: def D � Φ + R ◦ N A → B )( ω RA ) | Φ + E ω [ N ] R | ( id R ⊗ D B → ¯ R � = max R ¯ R ¯

  23. Comparison of Quantum Channels 2/2 Theorem (FB, 2016) Given two quantum channels N : A → B and N ′ : A → B ′ , the following are equivalent: 1. output degradability : there exists CPTP map C : N ′ = C ◦ N ; 2. coherence preorder : for any bipartite state ω RA , E ω [ N ] ≥ E ω [ N ′ ] , that is, H min ( R | B ) ( id ⊗N )( ω ) ≤ H min ( R | B ′ ) ( id ⊗N ′ )( ω ) . � applications to the theory of open quantum systems dynamics and, by adding symmetry constraints, to quantum thermodynamics 16/31

  24. Application 1: Open Quantum Systems Dynamics

  25. Discrete-Time Stochastic Processes • Let x i , for i = 0 , 1 , . . . , index the state of a system at time t = t i • if the system can be initialized at time t = t 0 , the process is fully described by the conditional distribution p ( x N , . . . , x 1 | x 0 ) • if the system evolving is quantum, we only have a � � N ( i ) quantum dynamical mapping Q 0 → Q i i =1 ,...,N • the process is divisible if there exist channels D ( i ) such that N ( i +1) = D ( i ) ◦ N ( i ) for all i • problem: to provide a fully information-theoretic characterization of divisibility 17/31

  26. Divisibility as “Quantum Information Flow” Theorem (2016-2018) Given an initial open quantum system Q 0 , a quantum dynamical mapping � � N ( i ) i ≥ 1 is divisibile if and only if, for any initial state ω RQ 0 , Q 0 → Q i H min ( R | Q 1 ) ≤ H min ( R | Q 2 ) ≤ · · · ≤ H min ( R | Q N ) . 18/31

  27. Application 2: Quantum Thermodynamics

  28. Resource Theory of Athermality and Asymmetry From [FB, arXiv:1505.00535], [FB and Gour, Phys. Rev. A 95, 012110 (2017)], and [Gour, Jennings, FB, Duan, and Marvian, Nat. Comm. 9, 5352 (2018)] • idea: to characterize thermal accessibility ρ → σ by comparing the dichotomies ( ρ, γ ) and ( σ, γ ) , for γ thermal state • classically, Blackwell’s theorem implies the thermomajorization relation • in the quantum case, in order to account for coherence, symmetry constraints can also be added to the Gibbs-preserving map 19/31

Recommend


More recommend