going beyond 2 4 in freiman s 2 4k theorem
play

Going beyond 2.4 in Freimans 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Going beyond 2.4 in Freimans 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol Serra Christoph Spiegel CANT 2018 New York, May 2018 I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition


  1. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Going beyond 2.4 in Freiman’s 2.4k-Theorem Pablo Candela Oriol Serra Christoph Spiegel CANT 2018 New York, May 2018

  2. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1)

  3. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } .

  4. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k :

  5. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1.

  6. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1. 2. For A = { 0 , 1 , 2 , 4 , . . . , 2 k − 2 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = � k � + 2. 2

  7. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS The sumset Definition Given a set A ⊂ G in some additive group G , we define its sumset as A + A = 2 A = { a + a ′ : a , a ′ ∈ A } ⊂ G . (1) This should not be confused with the dilate 2 · A = { 2 a : a ∈ A } . Example Consider the following two sets of size k : 1. For A = { 0 , . . . , k − 1 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = 2 k − 1. 2. For A = { 0 , 1 , 2 , 4 , . . . , 2 k − 2 } ⊂ Z we have | 2 A | = � k � + 2. 2 Inverse Problems: We are interested in understanding the structure of A when the doubling | 2 A | / | A | is small.

  8. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 .

  9. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression.

  10. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) .

  11. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression.

  12. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Kneser ’53) Any set A ⊆ Z n satisfies | 2 A| ≥ 2 |A + H | − | H | where H = { x ∈ Z n : x + 2 A ⊂ 2 A} is the stabilizer of the sumset.

  13. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Some classic results Proposition Any set A ⊂ Z satisfies | 2 A | ≥ 2 | A | − 1 . Equality holds if and only if A is an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Davenport ’35; Cauchy 1813) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfies | 2 A| ≥ min( 2 |A| − 1 , p ) . Theorem (Vosper ’56) Any set A ⊆ Z p satisfying |A| ≥ 2 and | 2 A| = 2 |A| − 1 ≤ p − 2 must be an arithmetic progression. Theorem (Kneser ’53) Any set A ⊆ Z n satisfies | 2 A| ≥ 2 |A + H | − | H | where H = { x ∈ Z n : x + 2 A ⊂ 2 A} is the stabilizer of the sumset. The corresponding inverse statement is due to Kemperman ’60.

  14. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 .

  15. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95.

  16. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider .

  17. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime.

  18. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a .

  19. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | .

  20. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | . 5. If | 2 A| = max( A ) we are done. If not, then Cauchy-Davenport gives us the contradiction | 2 A | ≥ 2 |A| − 1 + | A | = 3 | A | − 3.

  21. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Freiman’s 3 k − 4 Theorem in Z Theorem (Freiman ’66) Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A | ≤ 3 | A | − 4 is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A | − | A | + 1 . Proof due to Lev and Smeliansky ’95. � � � � A − min( A ) / gcd A − min( A ) 1. Normalize A , that is consider . 2. To simplify the proof, assume that a = max( A ) is prime. 3. Let A denote the canonical projection of A into Z a . � � 4. | 2 A | = | 2 A| + # x ∈ [ 0 , a ) : x , a + x ∈ 2 A + 1 ≥ | 2 A| + | A | . 5. If | 2 A| = max( A ) we are done. If not, then Cauchy-Davenport gives us the contradiction | 2 A | ≥ 2 |A| − 1 + | A | = 3 | A | − 3. Example For k ≥ 3 and x > 2 ( k − 2 ) the sets A x = { 0 , . . . , k − 2 } ∪ { x } all satisfy | 2 A x | = 3 | A x | − 3 but require arbitrarily large APs to be covered.

  22. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p .

  23. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p . Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A| ≤ 3 |A| − 4 as well as is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A| − |A| + 1.

  24. I NTRODUCTION T HE RESULT P ROOF I DEA R EMARKS Obtaining an analogue in Z p A similar result is conjectured to hold in Z p . Any set A ⊂ Z satisfying | 2 A| ≤ 3 |A| − 4 as well as is contained in an arithmetic progression of size at most | 2 A| − |A| + 1. Corollary to Green, Ruzsa ’06 |A| ≤ p / 10 250

Recommend


More recommend