varieties of de morgan monoids i minimality and
play

Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible Algebras T. Moraschini, 1 J.G. Raftery 2 J.J. Wannenburg 2 and 1 Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague 2 University of Pretoria, South Africa LATD 2017. Prague, Czech Republic T.


  1. Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I : Minimality and Irreducible Algebras T. Moraschini, 1 J.G. Raftery 2 J.J. Wannenburg 2 and 1 Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague 2 University of Pretoria, South Africa LATD 2017. Prague, Czech Republic T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  2. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  3. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  4. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  5. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  6. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  7. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  8. A De Morgan monoid A = � A ; · , ∧ , ∨ , ¬ , t � comprises ◮ a distributive lattice � A ; ∧ , ∨� ; ◮ a commutative monoid � A ; · , t � satisfying x � x · x ; ◮ an ‘involution’ ¬ : A − → A satisfying ¬¬ x = x and ⇒ x · ¬ z � ¬ y (so ¬ : � A ; ∧ , ∨� ∼ x · y � z = = � A ; ∨ , ∧� ). Defining x → y = ¬ ( x · ¬ y ) and f = ¬ t , we obtain the Law of Residuation: x · y � z ⇐ ⇒ x � y → z ; and ¬ x = x → f . DM = { all De Morgan monoids } is a variety. It is congruence distributive, extensible and permutable. T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  9. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  10. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  11. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  12. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  13. The relevance logic R t can be characterized as follows: ⊢ R t α (‘ α is a theorem of R t ’) iff DM | = t � α . More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for R t , we have γ 1 , . . . , γ n ⊢ R t α iff DM | = ( t � γ 1 & . . . & t � γ n ) = ⇒ t � α . There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the extensions of R t to the subquasivarieties of DM , taking axiomatic extensions onto subvarieties. We study the latter as a route to the former. Why? T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  14. Relevance logic began in protest at ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, e.g., the weakening axiom p → ( q → p ) . It has multiple interpretations, however, and now fits under the ideology-free umbrella of substructural logics. Relative to these, R t combines ∧ , ∨ distributivity with the contraction axiom ( p → ( p → q )) → ( p → q ) . Urquhart (1984): R t is undecidable. Algebraic effects? Less explored—philosophical equivocation over the status of t : distinguished or not? (In the absence of weakening, t is not equationally definable. The t –free reducts of De Morgan monoids don’t form a variety, as they are not closed under subalgebras. For the anti-isomorphism above, t must be distinguished.) T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

  15. Relevance logic began in protest at ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, e.g., the weakening axiom p → ( q → p ) . It has multiple interpretations, however, and now fits under the ideology-free umbrella of substructural logics. Relative to these, R t combines ∧ , ∨ distributivity with the contraction axiom ( p → ( p → q )) → ( p → q ) . Urquhart (1984): R t is undecidable. Algebraic effects? Less explored—philosophical equivocation over the status of t : distinguished or not? (In the absence of weakening, t is not equationally definable. The t –free reducts of De Morgan monoids don’t form a variety, as they are not closed under subalgebras. For the anti-isomorphism above, t must be distinguished.) T. Moraschini, J.G. Raftery and J.J. Wannenburg Varieties of De Morgan Monoids I

Recommend


More recommend