admissible tools in the kitchen of intuitionistic logic
play

Admissible tools in the kitchen of intuitionistic logic Matteo - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Admissible tools in the kitchen of intuitionistic logic Matteo Manighetti 1 Andrea Condoluci 2 Classical Logic and Computation, July 7, 2018 1 INRIA Saclay & LIX, Ecole Polytechnique 2 DISI, Universit` a di Bologna Intro: Admissibility


  1. Admissible tools in the kitchen of intuitionistic logic Matteo Manighetti 1 Andrea Condoluci 2 Classical Logic and Computation, July 7, 2018 1 INRIA Saclay & LIX, ´ Ecole Polytechnique 2 DISI, Universit` a di Bologna

  2. Intro: Admissibility in propositional intuitionistic logic

  3. Basic definitions Definition (Admissible and derivable rules) A rule ϕ/ψ is admissible if whenever ⊢ ϕ is provable, then ⊢ ψ is provable. It is derivable if ⊢ ϕ → ψ is provable Definition (Structural completeness) A logic is structurally complete if all admissible rules are derivable Note! Classical logic is structurally complete. Different from cut/weakening admissibility ! 1

  4. Basic definitions Definition (Admissible and derivable rules) A rule ϕ/ψ is admissible if whenever ⊢ ϕ is provable, then ⊢ ψ is provable. It is derivable if ⊢ ϕ → ψ is provable Definition (Structural completeness) A logic is structurally complete if all admissible rules are derivable Theorem (Harrop 1960) Intuitionistic propositional logic is not structurally complete Proof. Counterexample: ¬ α → ( γ 1 ∨ γ 2 ) / ( ¬ α → γ 1 ) ∨ ( ¬ α → γ 2 ) is admissible but not derivable We are interested in: admissible but non-derivable “principles” 1

  5. A bit of history • Friedman (1975) posed the question of whether the admissible rules of IPC are countable • Rybakov (1984) answered positively; De Jongh and Visser conjectured a basis for them • Iemhoff 2001 finally proved the conjecture with semantic methods • Less known: Rozi` ere 1993 independently obtained the same result with proof theoretic techniques 2

  6. Visser’s basis Theorem (Rozi` ere 1993, Iemhoff 2001) All admissible and non derivable rules are obtained by the usual intuitionistic rules and the following rules  � n j =1 (( α i → β i ) i =1 ... n → α j )      ∨     V n : ( α i → β i ) i =1 ... n → γ ∨ δ/ (( α i → β i ) i =1 ... n → γ )   ∨       (( α i → β i ) i =1 ... n → δ )  3

  7. Visser’s basis Visser’s basis is important not only for IPC : Theorem (Iemhoff 2005) If the rules of Visser’s basis are admissible in a logic, they form a basis for the admissible rules of that logic This has been applied to modal logics: G¨ odel Logic, G¨ odel-Dummet Logic. . . 4

  8. A Curry-Howard system for admissible rules

  9. Idea: explain Visser’s basis with Natural Deduction + Curry-Howard Advantages: • Axioms can be translated to rules right away • Simple way to assign lambda terms • Focus on reduction rules The rule should have the shape of a disjunction elimination 5

  10. Natural deduction rules for V n Add to a Natural Deduction system a rule for each of the V n : Γ , ( α i → β i ) i → γ 1 ⊢ ψ ∅ , ( α i → β i ) i ⊢ γ 1 ∨ γ 2 Γ , ( α i → β i ) i → γ 2 ⊢ ψ [Γ , ( α i → β i ) i → α j ⊢ ψ ] j =1 ... n Γ ⊢ ψ Idea: a disjunction elimination, parametrized over n implications Note The context of the main premise is empty. Otherwise we would be able to prove V n ! 6

  11. Term assignment Usual terms for IPC , plus the new one for the V-rules t , u , v ::= x | u v | λ x . t | efq t | � u , v � | proj i t | inj i t | case[ t | | y . u | y . v ] ✞ ☎ | V n [ � x . t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 | | z . � v ] (Visser) ✝ ✆ Γ , y : ( α i → β i ) i → γ 1 ⊢ u 1 : ψ Γ , y : ( α i → β i ) i → γ 2 ⊢ u 2 : ψ x : ( α i → β i ) i ⊢ t : γ 1 ∨ γ 2 [Γ , z : ( α i → β i ) i → α j ⊢ v j : ψ ] j =1 ... n � V n [ � x . t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 | | z . � v ] : ψ 7

  12. Reduction rules Evaluation contexts for IPC : W ::= [ · ] | W t | t W | efq W | proj i W | case[ W | | − | − ] Evaluation contexts for V n : structural closure of the reduction rules The usual rules for IPC , plus: • Visser-inj: V n [ � | z . � �→ u i { λ� x . t / y } ( i = 1 , 2) x .inj i t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 | v ] • Visser-app: V n [ � x . W [ x j t ] | | z . � �→ v j { λ� x . t / z } ( j = 1 . . . n ) | y . u 1 | y . u 2 | v ] 8

  13. The reduction rules tell us: • One of the disjuncts is proved directly, or • A proof for an α j was provided, to be used on a V-hypothesis This provides a succint explanation of what admissible rules can do The context is empty, so all the hypotheses are Visser-hypotheses, and we can move the terms around Subject reduction and termination are easy results! 9

  14. Logics characterized by admissible principles

  15. Logics characterized by admissible principles By lifting the restriction on the context, we can prove the axioms inside the logic We obtain Curry-Howard systems for the intermediate logics characterized by admissible principles 10

  16. Harrop’s rule and the Kreisel-Putnam logic The most famous admissible principle of IPC : Harrop’s rule ( ¬ α → ( γ 1 ∨ γ 2 )) → ( ¬ α → γ 1 ) ∨ ( ¬ α → γ 2 ) By adding it to IPC we obtain the Kreisel-Putnam logic KP (trivia: the first non-intuitionistic logic to be shown to have the disjunction property) This is just a particular case of the rule V1, with ⊥ for β : Γ , ( α → ⊥ ) → γ 1 ⊢ ψ Γ , ( α → ⊥ ) → γ 2 ⊢ ψ Γ , α → ⊥ ⊢ γ 1 ∨ γ 2 Γ , ( α → ⊥ ) → α ⊢ ψ ψ 11

  17. Harrop’s rule and the Kreisel-Putnam logic The terms for Harrop’s rule are a simplified version of V 1 : Γ , y : ¬ α → γ 1 ⊢ u 1 : ψ Γ , x : ¬ α ⊢ t : γ 1 ∨ γ 2 Γ , y : ¬ α → γ 2 ⊢ u 2 : ψ Γ ⊢ hop[ x . t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 ] : ψ In particular, we omit the third disjunct (it is trivial) 12

  18. Harrop’s rule and the Kreisel-Putnam logic Similarly, the reduction rules become �→ u i { λ� • Harrop-inj: hop[ x .inj i t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 ] x . t / y } • Harrop-app: hop[ x . H [ x t ] | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 ] �→ u i { ( λ x . efq x t ) / y } Note The app case looks different: there is no v term, but we know that any use of Harrop hypotheses must lead to a contradiction; thus conclude on either of u i 13

  19. Harrop’s rule and the Kreisel-Putnam logic Lemma (Classification) Let Γ ¬ ⊢ t : τ for t in n.f. and t not an exfalso: • If τ = ϕ → ψ , then t is an abstraction or a variable in Γ ¬ ; • If τ = ϕ ∨ ψ , then t is an injection; • If τ = ϕ ∧ ψ , then t is a pair; • If τ = ⊥ , then t = x v for some v and some x ∈ Γ ¬ ; Theorem (Disjunction property) If ⊢ t : ϕ ∨ ψ , then there is t ′ such that either ⊢ t ′ : ϕ or ⊢ t ′ : ψ . 14

  20. Rozi` ere’s logic AD What if we try to add the full V 1 principle? Theorem (Rozi` ere 1993) In the logic characterized by the axiom V 1 , all V i are derivable and all admissible rules are derivable Rozi` ere called this logic AD and showed that it isn’t classical logic. However: Theorem (Iemhoff 2001) The only logic with the disjunction property where all V n are admissible is IPC 15

  21. Rozi` ere’s logic AD We can as before provide a term assignment for AD: Γ , y : ( α → β ) → γ 1 ⊢ u 1 : ψ Γ , y : ( α → β ) → γ 2 ⊢ u 2 : ψ Γ , x : α → β ⊢ t : γ 1 ∨ γ 2 Γ , z : ( α → β ) → α ⊢ v : ψ Γ ⊢ V 1 [ x . t | | y . u 1 | y . u 2 | | z . v ] : ψ Although it doesn’t have the disjunction property, AD seems an interesting and not well studied logic. Rozi` ere posed the problem of finding a functional interpretation for it; we go in this direction by providing a term assignment to proofs 16

  22. Future work

  23. Future work The logic based on admissible principles way: • More in-depth study of AD The admissibility way: • Port the system for Visser’s rules to other (modal) logics • Study admissible principles of intuitionistic arithmetic ( HA ) • . . . and admissible principles of first-order logic 17

  24. References Rosalie Iemhoff. “Intermediate logics and Visser’s rules”. In: Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46.1 (2005), pp. 65–81. Rosalie Iemhoff. “On the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic”. In: The Journal of Symbolic Logic 66.1 (Mar. 2001), pp. 281–294. Paul Rozi` ere. “Admissible rules and backward derivation in intuitionistic logic”. In: Math. Struct. in Comp. Science 3.3 (1993), pp. 129–136. 18

Recommend


More recommend