non cupping and non mitoticity in the lr degrees
play

Non-cupping and non-mitoticity in the LR-degrees Anthony Morphett - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Non-cupping and non-mitoticity in the LR-degrees Anthony Morphett Leeds Logic Seminar 10 October 2007 Outline LR-reducibility and LR-degrees Non-cupping and LR-completeness Mitoticity and non-mitoticity Algorithmic Randomness


  1. Non-cupping and non-mitoticity in the LR-degrees Anthony Morphett Leeds Logic Seminar 10 October 2007

  2. Outline ◮ LR-reducibility and LR-degrees ◮ Non-cupping and LR-completeness ◮ Mitoticity and non-mitoticity

  3. Algorithmic Randomness Consider infinite binary strings x = x 0 x 1 x 2 . . . , x i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . When is such a string random ? Three ideas:

  4. Algorithmic Randomness Consider infinite binary strings x = x 0 x 1 x 2 . . . , x i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . When is such a string random ? Three ideas: • x should be unpredictable: gambler should not win if betting on consecutive bits

  5. Algorithmic Randomness Consider infinite binary strings x = x 0 x 1 x 2 . . . , x i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . When is such a string random ? Three ideas: • x should be unpredictable: gambler should not win if betting on consecutive bits • x should be typical: should not have any distinguishing properties

  6. Algorithmic Randomness Consider infinite binary strings x = x 0 x 1 x 2 . . . , x i ∈ { 0 , 1 } . When is such a string random ? Three ideas: • x should be unpredictable: gambler should not win if betting on consecutive bits • x should be typical: should not have any distinguishing properties • x should be incompressible: no way to describe (initial segments of) x except by x itself

  7. Definitions 2 <ω : space of finite binary strings 2 ω : Cantor space; infinite binary strings 2 ω as a topological space: basic open sets are [ σ ] := { x ∈ 2 ω : σ ⊂ x } 2 ω as a measure space: Lebesgue measure given by := 2 −| σ | � � µ [ σ ]

  8. A c.e. open set is a set of finite strings U ⊂ 2 <ω such that: • U is computably enumerable; • if σ, τ ∈ U then σ �⊂ τ - the basic open sets [ σ ] , [ τ ] are disjoint. Also known as Σ 0 1 -class.

  9. Martin-L¨ of Randomness x is random if it is typical - has no distinguishing features � � A test is a sequence U i i ∈ ω of c.e. open sets such that U i +1 ⊆ U i and ≤ 2 − i . � � µ U i x ∈ 2 ω is random if for all tests � � U i , � x / ∈ U i . Theorem: There is a universal test ˜ U i such that ∈ ∩ ˜ x is random iff x / U i .

  10. x is random if it is unpredictable - a gambler should not win if betting on consecutive bits ◮ no c.e. martingale (gambling strategy) succeeds on x in the limit x is random if it is incompressible - there is no way to describe (initial segments of) x except by x itself ◮ the shortest Turing program that outputs x ↾ n is as long as x ↾ n ◮ x ↾ n is hard-coded into the program ◮ high Kolmogorov complexity

  11. Low for randomness These definitions relativise: add oracle A to tests to get A -randomness. � U A ∈ x is A -random if x / i for universal oracle test U i . A is low for random if x is random ⇒ x is A -random “Everything random is still A -random” - using A as oracle doesn’t help detect patterns.

  12. Low for randomness • Computable sets are low for random • Non-computable low for random sets exist • All low-for-randoms are ∆ 0 2 and low

  13. LR-reducibility Low-for-randomness suggests the definition of LR-reducibility: Definition A ≤ LR B iff ∀ x ∈ 2 ω , x is B-random ⇒ x is A-random . A cannot detect any more patterns than B .

  14. • Equivalence relation: A ≡ LR B if A ≤ LR B and B ≤ LR A • LR-degrees are equivalence classes of sets under ≡ LR • 0 LR = deg LR ∅ consists of all low-for-random sets Compared to Turing degrees: • A ≤ T B ⇒ A ≤ LR B • each LR-degree contains infinitely many Turing degrees

  15. Theorem (Kjos-Hanssen) A ≤ LR B iff ∀ A-c.e. open sets U A , µ ( U A ) < 1 , U A ⊆ V B ( ∗ ) for some B-c.e. open set V B with µ ( V B ) < 1 . In fact, ( ∗ ) need hold only for a single U - member of universal A -randomness test. → gives a means of creating and destroying LR-reductions.

  16. Non-cupping and LR-degrees A c.e. set A is non-cuppable if ∀ c.e. sets X , A ⊕ X ≥ T ∅ ′ ⇒ X ≥ T ∅ ′ - you can’t get to ∅ ′ by adding the information of another c.e. set except ∅ ′ itself NCup = { non-cuppable c.e. Turing degrees }

  17. Non-cupping in Turing degrees studied by ◮ Yates, Cooper 1972 ◮ Harrington (D. Miller), 1970’s, 80’s ◮ Li, Slaman & Yang; Yang & Yu; tree constructions

  18. Non-cupping in Turing degrees studied by ◮ Yates, Cooper 1972 ◮ Harrington (D. Miller), 1970’s, 80’s ◮ Li, Slaman & Yang; Yang & Yu; tree constructions NCup forms an ideal in c.e. Turing degrees: ◮ closed under ⊕ ◮ closed downward under ≤ T

  19. Theorem (Cooper, Yates) There is a nontrivial non-cuppable c.e. degree. Theorem (Harrington) 1. There is a high non-cuppable c.e. degree. 2. Moreover, for any high b there is a high a such that a cannot be cupped to b : ∀ x a ∪ x ≥ b ⇒ x ≥ b .

  20. Theorem There is a non-cuppable c.e. set A ≡ LR ∅ ′ (LR-complete).

  21. Theorem There is a non-cuppable c.e. set A ≡ LR ∅ ′ (LR-complete). A ≥ LR ∅ ′ ⇒ A is high...

  22. Theorem There is a non-cuppable c.e. set A ≡ LR ∅ ′ (LR-complete). A ≥ LR ∅ ′ ⇒ A is high... so this is a partial strengthening of Harrington’s result.

  23. Capping and non-cupping Cap = cappable degrees, half of minimal pair

  24. Capping and non-cupping Cap = cappable degrees, half of minimal pair Theorem (Barmpalias & Montalb´ an) There is a cappable LR-complete c.e. set.

  25. Capping and non-cupping Cap = cappable degrees, half of minimal pair Theorem (Barmpalias & Montalb´ an) There is a cappable LR-complete c.e. set. NCup is a subideal of Cap

  26. The construction To make A ≥ LR ∅ ′ : ◮ if σ appears in U ∅ ′ then put it in V A with large use u ◮ if σ is removed from U ∅ ′ due to ∅ ′ -change, put u into A ◮ this may remove some other legitimate interval ρ with use > u ; put ρ back into V A with the same use.

  27. Making A non-cuppable To make A non-cuppable we would like to build Turing functional ∆ to satisfy N e : Γ A ⊕ W = ∅ ′ ⇒ ∆ W = ∅ ′ for all Turing functionals Γ and c.e. sets W . Idea: ◮ Wait until Γ AW ( p ) ↓ = ∅ ′ ( p ); ◮ define ∆ W ( p ) = Γ AW ( p ); ◮ restrain A ↾ use Γ AW ( p ).

  28. Non-cupping strategy - naive Problems: 1. if in fact Γ AW = ∅ ′ , we must act infinitely often ⇒ N e imposes infinite restraint ⇒ must spread actions over infinitely many subrequirements M e , p : Γ AW ( p ) = ∅ ′ ( p ) ⇒ ∆ W ( p ) ↓ = ∅ ′ ( p ) 2. need to be able to invalidate ∆ W ( p ) definitions to right of current path • must maintain A -restraint while ∆ W ( p ) is defined • need a way to force W -change

  29. Non-cupping strategy - improved We build auxiliary c.e. set D . Let K = D ∪ ∅ ′ ( ≡ T ∅ ′ ) N Parent node: τ - waits for expansionary stage for Γ AW = K M p Subrequirement node: α - chooses flip-point d / ∈ D - waits until Γ AW ( d ) ↓ - defines ∆ W ( p ) ↓ = Γ AW ( p ) = ∅ ′ ( p ) with use u = use Γ AW ( d )

  30. If we need to invalidate α ’s ∆ W ( p ) definition: ◮ enumerate d into D ◮ K changes, so Γ AW = K is destroyed ◮ if Γ AW = K then Γ AW must change to restore agreement with K ◮ but A is restrained, so W must change below use Γ AW ( d ) = use ∆ W ( p ) ◮ previous definition ∆ σ ( p ) is invalidated as now σ �⊂ W

  31. Putting them together - non-cuppable and LR-complete ◮ Restraints by non-cupping requirements prevent us from removing intervals from V A ◮ Give each requirement a quota ǫ ◮ Allow it to capture at most ǫ junk intervals ◮ Choose ǫ ’s so that ǫ < 1 � 2 Thus V A � U ∅ ′ � � � � µ < µ + ǫ < 1 .

  32. In tree setting, this means: ◮ allowing only one restraint on each level of the tree U ∅ ′ � ◮ providing non-cupping requirements with an estimate to µ � ◮ resetting nodes if their measure estimate is wrong

  33. Notable features of the construction Regarding the LR-complete strategy: ◮ Uses measure-guessing backup strategies as in previous LR-complete constructions ◮ Can’t always reset a node when its measure guess is wrong - use non-cupping clearing procedure instead ◮ Permanent restraints can capture more than their quota ǫ of junk intervals ◮ But still ensure that � ǫ ( M p ) < 3 ǫ ( N ) M p

  34. Notable features of the construction Regarding the non-cuppable strategy: ◮ Must delay the definition of ∆ W ( p ) until V A ↾ u − V A ↾ R − U ∅ ′ � � µ < ǫ That is, until we won’t capture more than ǫ junk. ◮ Must clear definitions by nodes to the left, as well as above, before visiting a node

  35. Mitoticity and LR-degrees Definition A c.e. set A is mitotic if there are disjoint c.e. sets X , Y s.t. A = X ∪ Y ; and X ≡ T Y ≡ T A . “ A can be split into two c.e. sets of the same degree”

  36. Mitoticity and LR-degrees Definition A c.e. set A is mitotic if there are disjoint c.e. sets X , Y s.t. A = X ∪ Y ; and X ≡ T Y ≡ T A . “ A can be split into two c.e. sets of the same degree” ◮ there are non-mitotic c.e. sets

  37. Mitoticity and LR-degrees Definition A c.e. set A is mitotic if there are disjoint c.e. sets X , Y s.t. A = X ∪ Y ; and X ≡ T Y ≡ T A . “ A can be split into two c.e. sets of the same degree” ◮ there are non-mitotic c.e. sets ◮ they can be complete ( ≡ T ∅ ′ )

Recommend


More recommend