iterated ultrapowers and automorphisms ali enayat pisa
play

Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1 - PDF document

Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1 Our story begins with: Question (H asenj ager): Does PA have a model with a nontrivial auto- morphism? Answer (Ehrenfeucht and Mostowski): Yes, indeed given any


  1. Iterated Ultrapowers and Automorphisms Ali Enayat Pisa, May 2006 1

  2. Our story begins with: • Question (H¨ asenj¨ ager): Does PA have a model with a nontrivial auto- morphism? • Answer (Ehrenfeucht and Mostowski): Yes, indeed given any first order theory T with an infinite model M � T , and any linear order L , there is a model M L of T such that Aut ( L ) ֒ → Aut ( M L ) . • Corollaries: (a) PA , RCF, and ZFC have models with rich automorphism groups. (b) Nonstandard models of analysis with rich automorphism groups exist. 2

  3. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (1) • Gaifman saw a radically different proof of the EM Theorem: iterate the ultrapower construction along a prescribed linear order. • Suppose (a) M = ( M, · · · ) is a structure, (b) U is an ultrafilter over P ( N ), and (c) L is a linear order. we wish to describe the L -iterated ultrapower � M ∗ := M . U , L 3

  4. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers, Continued (2) • A key definition (reminiscent of Fubini): ( X ) a � �� � U 2 := { X ⊆ N 2 : { a ∈ N : { b ∈ N : ( a, b ) ∈ X }∈ U} ∈ U . • More generally, for each n ∈ N + : U n +1 := { X ⊆ N n +1 : { a ∈ N : ( X ) a ∈ U n } ∈ U} , where ( X ) a := { ( b 1 , · · · , b n ) : ( a, b 1 , · · · , b n ) ∈ X } 4

  5. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (3) • Let Υ be the set of terms τ of the form f ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) , where n ∈ N + , f : N n → M and ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) ∈ [ L ] n . • The universe M ∗ of M ∗ consists of equivalence classes { [ τ ] : τ ∈ Υ } , where the equivalence relation ∼ at work is defined as follows: given ′ ′ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) and g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) from Υ, first suppose that � � ′ ′ ∈ [ L ] r + s ; l 1 , · · · , l r , l 1 , · · · , l s ′ ′ let p := r + s , and define: f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) ∼ g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) iff: { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i 1 , · · · , i r ) = g ( i r +1 , · · · , i p ) } ∈ U p . 5

  6. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (4) More generally: ′ ′ • Given f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) and g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) from Υ , let ′ ′ P := { l 1 , · · · , l r } ∪ { l 1 , · · · , l s } , p := | P | , and relabel the elements of P in increasing order as l 1 < · · · < l p . This relabelling gives rise to increasing sequences ( j 1 , j 2 , · · · , j r ) and ( k 1 , k 2 , · · · , k s ) of indices between 1 and p such that l 1 = l j 1 , l 2 = l j 2 , · · · , l r = l j r and l ′ ′ ′ 1 = l k 1 , l 2 = l k 2 , · · · , l s = l k s . ′ ′ Then define: f ( l 1 , · · · , l r ) ∼ g ( l 1 , · · · , l s ) iff { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) = g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ) } ∈ U p . 6

  7. The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (5) • We can also use the previous relabelling to define the operations and relations of M ∗ as follows, e.g., [ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r )] ⊙ M ∗ [ g ( l ′ ′ 1 , · · · , l s )] := [ v ( l 1 , · · · , l p )] where v : N n → M by v ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) := f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) ⊙ M g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ); [ f ( l 1 , · · · , l r )] ⊳ M ∗ [ g ( l ′ ′ 1 , · · · , l s )] iff { ( i 1 , · · · , i p ) ∈ N p : f ( i j 1 , · · · , i j r ) ⊳ M ∗ g ( i k 1 , · · · , i k s ) } ∈ U p . The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (6) • For m ∈ M , let c m be the constant m -function on N , i.e. , c m : N → { m } . For any l ∈ L , we can identify the element [ c m ( l )] with m . • We shall also identify [ id ( l )] with l, where id : N → N is the identity function (WLOG N ⊆ M ) . • Therefore M ∪ L can be viewed as a subset of M ∗ . 7

  8. • Theorem. For every formula ϕ ( x 1 , ··· , x n ) , and every ( l 1 , · · · , l n ) ∈ [ L ] n : M ∗ � ϕ ( l 1 , l 2 , · · · , l n ) ⇐ ⇒ { ( i 1 , · · · , i n ) ∈ N n : M � ϕ ( i 1 , · · · , i n ) } ∈ U n . The EM Theorem via Iterated Ultrapowers (7) • Corollary 1. M ≺ M ∗ , and L is a set of order indiscernibles in M ∗ . • Corollary 2. Every automorphism j of L lifts to an automorphism ˆ  of M ∗ via ˆ  ([ f ( l 1 , · · · , l n )]) = [ f ( j ( l 1 ) , · · · , j ( l n ))] . Moreover, the map j �→ ˆ  is a group embedding of Aut ( L ) into Aut ( M ∗ ) . 8

  9. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (1) • If M has definable Skolem functions, then we can form the Skolem ultrapower � M F , U as follows: (a) Suppose B is the Boolean algebra of parametrically definable subsets of M , and U is an ultrafilter over B . (b) Let F be the family of functions from M into M that are paramet- rically definable in M . (c) The universe of the M ∗ is { [ f ] : f ∈ F} , where f ∼ g ⇐ ⇒ { m ∈ M : f ( m ) = g ( m ) } ∈ U 9

  10. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (2) • Theorem (MacDowell-Specker) Every model of PA has an elementary end extension. Proof : for an appropriate choice of U , � M ≺ e M . F , U • For models of some Skolemized theories, such as PA , the process of ultrapower formation can be iterated along any linear order. • For each parametrically definable X ⊆ M, and m ∈ M, ( X ) m = { x ∈ M : � m, x � ∈ X } . • U is an iterable ultrafilter over B if for every definable X ⊆ M , { m ∈ M : ( X ) m ∈ U} . 10

  11. Skolem-Gaifman Ultrapowers (3) • Theorem (Gaifman) If U is iterable, and L is a linear order, then � M ≺ e, cons M . F , U , L • Theorem (Gaifman). For an appropriate choice of iterable U , (a) Aut ( � M ; M ) ∼ = Aut ( L ) . F , U , L � (b) M has an automorphism j such that F , U , L fix ( j ) = M. • Theorem (Schmerl). Suppose G ≤ Aut ( L ) for some linear order L . (a) G ∼ = Aut ( M ) for some M � PA. (b) G ∼ = Aut ( F ) for some ordered field F . 11

  12. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (1) • A cut I of M � PA is an initial segment of M with no last element . • For a cut I of M , SSy I ( M ) is the collection of sets of the form X ∩ I, where X is parametrically definable in M . • I is strong in M iff ( I , SSy I ( M )) � ACA 0 . • M is recursively saturated if for every m ∈ M, every recursive finitely realizable type over ( M , m ) is realized in M . • For j ∈ Aut ( M ) , I fix ( j ) := { x ∈ dom ( j ) : ∀ y ≤ x j ( y ) = y } , fix ( j ) := { x ∈ M : j ( x ) = x } 12

  13. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (2) Suppose M � PA is ctble, rec. sat., and I is a cut of M . • Theorem (Smory´ nski) I = I fix ( j ) for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) iff I is closed under exponentiation . • Theorem (Kaye-Kossak-Kotlarski ) I = fix ( j ) for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) iff I is a strong elementary submodel of M . 13

  14. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (3) • Theorem (Kaye-Kossak-Kotlarski) N isstrongin M � �� � M isarithmeticallysaturated iff for some j ∈ Aut ( M ), jismaximal � �� � fix ( j ) isthecollectionofdefinableelementsof M . • Theorem (Schmerl) Aut ( Q ) ֒ → Aut ( M ) . 14

  15. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (4) • Theorem (E). If I is a closed under exponentiation, then there is a group embedding j �→ ˆ  from Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ) such that: (a) I fix (ˆ  ) = I for every nontrivial j ∈ Aut ( Q );  ) ∼ (b) fix(ˆ = M for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . • Idea of the proof: Fix c ∈ M \ I, let c := { x ∈ M : x < c } , B := P M ( c ), and F be the family of functions from ( c ) n → M that are coded in M . For an appropriate choice of U , � M ∼ M overI. = F , U , Q This sort of iteration was implicitly considered by Mills and Paris. 15

  16. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (5) • A new type of iteration that subsumes both Gaifman and Paris-Mills iteration: starting with I ⊆ e M � N , withI ⊆ strong N , (a) F = { f ↾ I n : f par. definable in N } ; (b) B := SSy I ( N ); (c) U an appropriate ultrafilter over B . • Theorem (E). Suppose M is arithmetically saturated. There is a group embedding j �→ ˆ  from Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ) such that ˆ  is maximal for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . 16

  17. Automorphisms of Countable Recursively Saturated Models of PA (6) • Conjecture (Schmerl). Suppose M is arithmetically saturated, and M 0 ≺ M . Then fix ( j ) ∼ = M 0 for some j ∈ Aut ( M ) . • Theorem (Kossak) Every countable model of PA is isomorphic to some fix ( j ), for some j ∈ Aut ( M ), and some countable arithmetically satu- rated model M . • Theorem (Kossak) The cardinality of { fix ( j ) : j ∈ Aut ( M ) } / ∼ = is either 2 ℵ 0 or 1, depending on whether M is arithmetically saturated or not. • Theorem (E). Suppose M 0 ≺ M , and M is arithmetically saturated . There are M 1 ≺ M with M 0 ∼ = M 1 , and an embedding j �→ ˆ  of Aut ( Q ) into Aut ( M ), such that fix(ˆ  ) = M 1 for every fixed point free j ∈ Aut ( Q ) . 17

Recommend


More recommend